Hacker News new | past | comments | ask | show | jobs | submit login
Prediction Markets (gwern.net)
192 points by gwern on Oct 3, 2013 | hide | past | favorite | 77 comments



There are several fundamental problems with prediction markets:

1) Every market participant is not a savvy investor. InTrade was notorious for political bias and emotional trading (check out the comment section). The idea is that a true insider will place a large bet that provides valuable information to the market. This is rarely the case. Most of the people bet based on what they want to happen rather than what they know will happen. [1] This problem is compounded by the fact that most of the bets on intrade in particular were rather small, hundreds of dollars. People tend to speak more accurately with their wallets as opposed to their mouths, but only with significant amounts of money on the line.

2) The markets themselves are never large enough. The system doesn't work unless the people that place big bets are experts or insiders. The majority of people aren't familiar with the concept of prediction markets, much less any particular sites. One of the best cases for an information market would be someone who works on a political campaign placing a big bet for or against their candidate based on inside knowledge. But something like this can't happen until the average political staffer has heard of a prediction market site, which we are still a long way away from.

3) The best way to make money from a market is to out think the other participants. Accurately calculating prices based on the current supply and demand situation works too, but it's slower and more difficult. Instead of asking "Who do I think will be elected president?" people might themselves "Who do the other participants think will be elected president?" This leads to a functioning market but it doesn't do much for the goal of aggregating knowledge to make accurate predictions.

I like the concept of prediction markets because I love the idea of utilizing collective intelligence. But I'm constantly disappointed by the implementations that I see. It's a very tricky thing to do but I think that whoever finally figures it out will have built something valuable for all of us.

[1] http://go.bloomberg.com/political-capital/2012-06-29/intrade...


1) The presence of non-savvy participants should encourage users, after all it means that there is money to be made! If the only users were insider traders, you'd be mad to join in.

2) Betfair had US election markets with hundreds of thousands of dollars at stake, and this is a site that blocks US users. So the interest and the money is there. (The legal/political problems in many countries are still a big hurdle though) Admittedly, the volumes are still peanuts compared to most sports markets...

3) Not really true. You win a bet if you get the result right, e.g. You predict the result of an event. You don't win by guessing the beliefs of others. Sure, you can trade in and out of a market as opinion changes, but you are still betting on a result and not an opinion.


You win a bet if you get the result right, e.g. You predict the result of an event.

This isn't really true, at least not for most real prediction markets, because bets can be traded. The article gives an example: the author bought bets on McCain for the 2008 election early on when they were cheap, then sold them shortly before the Republican convention when they were fetching much higher prices. In other words, he wasn't really betting on McCain winning; he was betting on enough people believing McCain had good odds of winning that he could sell his McCain bets at a profit--i.e., he was indeed winning by guessing the beliefs of others.


Well, first of all, he didn't have to trade! Bets are be settled normally on the event happening or not, regardless of trading or of the motivation of the bettor.

Secondly, just because he traded, doesn't mean he was solely betting on the beliefs of others. Odds can change over time because of betting activity caused by events, news and information. e.g. news stories, statements, etc. If those changes mean that the OP could trade out, good for him.

Another example: Let's say NASA spots a huge asteriod in space, zooming towards earth. To pass the time, people are betting on whether or not it hits. (Let's not worry about how the bets get paid out!) Common consensus is that there is a 10% chance of a collision, but using your awesome physics knowledge, you reckon there's actually a 30% chance, give-or-take. So, you bet ON the asteroid hitting.

A few days later, a news release from an esteemed astronomer reports that her calculations show that the asteroid is more likely to collide than previously thought. As a result, betting activity on the exchange adjusts and the consensus moves to 28%. Now, you might well be tempted to trade out of your bet at this point, and "lock in" a profit. After all, the odds are close to your own beliefs.

Did you trade because of guessing the beliefs of others? No. You traded because the odds changed as a result of information changes, new info becoming public knowledge. You thought the original bet was value, and you traded out at zero cost to get certainty.


What you say about the market odds changing because of changes in information known to the participants is of course true, but it misses my point. The very fact that bets can be traded means that people can profit by betting on the beliefs of others, not on the actual outcome of the event the betting is based on.

The example of the McCain bets for the 2008 election is a case in point: if the author's bet would only have paid off on the actual outcome, he would have lost! The only reason he was able to make money at all was that he found other people willing to buy his bets.

Similarly, in your asteroid example, yes, you sold your bets because information changed, but the reason you were able to make money doing so was that there were other people willing to buy your bets--which means their expectations about the outcome must have been different from yours (if they were the same as yours, no one would buy your bet, because the trade is zero sum). So you are making money based on others' beliefs about the outcome, not based on the actual outcome.

For example, if the asteroid ultimately does not hit, then all your "yes" bets are losing bets; the only reason you made money was that you sold your bets before the fact that they were losing bets became known for certain, just like the article's author did with his McCain bets. But also, even if the asteroid ultimately does hit, your payoff doesn't depend on that, because you sold your bets; someone else, who bought them, ended up making the profit you could have made if you had held them until the outcome was known. So once again, you made your money based on other people's beliefs about the outcome, not based on the actual outcome. (You even agree with this, when you say that you sell when the market odds are close to your own beliefs: the market odds are determined by the average beliefs of all the participants, not by the actual outcome.)


As a point of fact, the article writer's positions on Obama and McCain that he discusses in the text were to win the nomination, not the general election. He would have won the McCain bet with the full dollar if he had hung on to it.

You can read the raw data, less ambiguous than the text, below the main article.


the article writer's positions on Obama and McCain that he discusses in the text were to win the nomination, not the general election

You're right, and I hadn't grasped that from the article. See my response to the article's author upthread.


> In other words, he wasn't really betting on McCain winning

Actually, I was. I was betting that either I would hold the shares to completion and receive a full payout or enough information would emerge that McCain's odds of winning were higher than then estimated.

> The example of the McCain bets for the 2008 election is a case in point: if the author's bet would only have paid off on the actual outcome, he would have lost!

And you misunderstood the transactions in question. They weren't whether McCain would win the 2008 election, they were whether he would win the nomination. By the time I sold them, he had locked up dozens more delegates than necessary to guarantee his nomination, and my reason for selling was as stated: the contract was basically settled, I just wanted to avoid him keeling over and costing me my well-earned gains. As it happened, McCain did not die or quit, and so the contract paid out in full. I had been completely right, and was appropriately rewarded.


you misunderstood the transactions in question. They weren't whether McCain would win the 2008 election, they were whether he would win the nomination.

You're right, I hadn't grasped this from reading the article. However, a key point I made still stands:

my reason for selling was as stated: the contract was basically settled, I just wanted to avoid him keeling over and costing me my well-earned gains.

And the reason you were able to do this is that there were people willing to buy your bets; in other words, that there were people who evaluated the risk of him keeling over differently than you did. If there weren't any such people, you would have had to bear that risk yourself.

In other words, the actual bet in question was not whether McCain would "win" the nomination; that had already been settled--he had enough delegates to guarantee that outcome (and the prediction market could just as easily have been based on the bet "will McCain lock up enough delegates to guarantee the nomination"). The bet was whether he would actually become the nominee, i.e., would actually go through the formal procedure that made him the official candidate; that was the outcome that triggered the payoff, and you did not get paid based on that actual outcome; you got paid based on other people's estimate of the probability of that outcome being different from yours. You were only able to sell your bets because your estimate of the probability of that outcome was different than that of the people who bought your bets, based on your higher estimate of the risk of him keeling over; if everyone in the market had estimated the risk of him keeling over as being higher than your estimate, no one would have bought your bets at any price you were willing to sell them for.

In other words: you did not "win" the actual bet in question, because you did not hold your bet until the actual outcome was triggered--if you had, you would have won more money than you actually received. If you had correctly predicted that he would not keel over before formally becoming the nominee, you could have gotten that extra money yourself. Of course I understand why you didn't do that: you were willing to give up a few cents on the dollar as a hedge against risk. But that doesn't change the fact that you did do it, and therefore you did not win by making a correct prediction about the actual outcome.


I think you're drawing some sort of weird absolutist distinction here I don't understand at all. Why did the share prices go from the 10s of % to 95% or more? Because I correctly forecast everything important about the bet: that McCain had a much higher chance of winning the nomination than everyone else did, and the market was wrong. I won that bet in spades and realized a return. Why does it matter that at some point I closed out my contract?

(And actually no, it doesn't have to be differing estimates. It could also be risk aversion, liquidity constraints, noise, or a bunch of other things.)


Why did the share prices go from the 10s of % to 95% or more?

Because people were buying the shares: supply and demand. And of course they were buying them because the general opinion on McCain's chances was changing. I'm not disputing that.

Because I correctly forecast everything important about the bet: that McCain had a much higher chance of winning the nomination than everyone else did, and the market was wrong.

Yes: you basically did the same thing investors do when they believe a stock is undervalued. I'm not disputing that either.

Why does it matter that at some point I closed out my contract?

Because you were able to close it out for any reason at all other than the actual outcome on which the bet was based. The claim to which I originally responded in this subthread (which wasn't made by you, btw) was this: "You win a bet if you get the result right, e.g. You predict the result of an event. You don't win by guessing the beliefs of others. Sure, you can trade in and out of a market as opinion changes, but you are still betting on a result and not an opinion."

Strictly speaking, this is only true if bets (or shares, or whatever you want to call them) cannot be traded. If bets can be traded, then other possible strategies open up that are not possible if bets cannot be traded. You played one such strategy: you correctly predicted that a certain bet (on McCain winning the nomination) was undervalued, so you bought it and waited for the price to go up. When the price had risen enough that the extra gain from continuing to hold the bet was less, to you, than the risk of him keeling over (i.e., less than the benefit to you of risk aversion), you sold your bet.

Such a strategy is not possible if bets cannot be traded. Suppose trading of bets had not been allowed in your case; you would have had to make your original bet knowing that you could not sell it, but would have to hold it until the actual outcome--i.e., you would not have the opportunity to lay off the risk. That would have changed the expected benefit to you from the transaction. (Whether it would have made a difference in what you actually did, I can't say; but it certainly would have changed at least some of the factors on which you based your decision.)

It is quite true that you chose to play this strategy based on your (correct) prediction about the outcome, that McCain would get the nomination. But that doesn't change the fact that the strategy itself, the one you actually played, depended on their being other players in the market to whom you could sell the bet when your desire for risk aversion became large enough. In other words, it depended on trading of bets being allowed, and on other players having different valuations of the shares than you did, so that you could find someone to trade with. So even if you "won" in the sense of correctly predicting the outcome, and realizing a payoff based on that prediction, the opinions of other players in the market still made a difference. That's what I was trying to emphasize.

it doesn't have to be differing estimates. It could also be risk aversion, liquidity constraints, noise, or a bunch of other things.

Technically, yes, there are two general kinds of reasons: differing estimates, and differing values. But in practice they basically amount to the same thing: your expected benefit from various possible courses of action is different from someone else's. That's the key thing that makes things like trading bets possible at all (that and whether or not the particular market in question allows trading bets to begin with).


Exactly right.

"The idea is that a true insider will place a large bet that provides valuable information to the market."

Yes, and in practice, the true insider has every incentive to provide false information to the market, so as to manipulate people's expectations. The insider seeks alpha by trading on the resultant volatility in that prediction's pricing.

Let's imagine I am the perfect insider. I have a crystal ball that somehow gives me 100% flawless predictive ability into the outcome of a particular bet (say, the next Republican primary). I could make a fair amount of money by betting on the winner, or I could make a lot more money by manipulating the information in the marketplace, creating volatility in the prices of the prediction bets, capitalizing on each fluctuation, while still holding some inventory in the correct outcome. If I knew the winner was going to be Joe Blow, I could bottom out Joe Blow's price by seeding false information, buy him low, then do the same for other candidates.

Of course, the real world doesn't have perfectly predictive crystal balls. But because prediction markets are too small to cause real-world changes (i.e., there's no observer effect), manipulating information would not have a demonstrable effect on outcomes (as it would in a larger, more efficient marketplace). Ergo, as the insider with better info than most, my incentive is to mislead. I do not need a crystal ball to make a killing; I just need slightly better information than the rest of the market. The smaller the market, the more likely it is that my inside information is better than the market's.

In a much bigger market, I couldn't get away with this strategy. At least not very easily or reliably. My seeding misinformation about Joe Blow would actually hurt Joe Blow's fundraising ability, thereby creating a self-fulfilling prophecy, thereby causing the market price to more accurately reflect reality. If I massively short Joe Blow, Joe Blow's chances actually drop. I'd get less alpha. But as you've said, the markets are way too closed and small to exhibit such an effect -- so I can rig the game accordingly.


I could make a lot more money by manipulating the information in the marketplace, creating volatility in the prices of the prediction bets, capitalizing on each fluctuation, while still holding some inventory in the correct outcome.

And one extreme version of this is mounting a credible campaign then "throwing" the race or withdrawing abruptly. This is attractive whenever the possible winnings in the prediction market are large and the market is insufficiently regulated. In ordinary financial markets, there can be special scrutiny paid to shorts, but the zero-sum game structure of a prediction market loses the distinction.


True, although not every trade is zero-sum per se, depending upon the prediction market. More sophisticated trading strategies involve profiting off of the changes in probability of a given outcome over time (or at least the changes in perception of that probability), rather than simply buying and holding a one-sided bet on fixed odds. They amount to psychological manipulation of the market, buying and selling the same positions over time at local minima and maxima.

You're absolutely right about the power to "throw" a prediction market, however, provided the right parties can conspire to do so. This is essentially what Arnold Rothstein and associates did in fixing the 1919 World Series. Most people casually assume the fixers bribed the players to throw the game, then profited off the results. In actuality, their strategy was slightly more nuanced. They spread the rumor that the game had been fixed long before they actually fixed the game, thereby forcing an adjustment of odds on (illegal, unregulated) gambling books. This allowed them to hedge long against their predominantly short bet, covering them adequately in the event that the fix was insufficient to adjust the game's most likely outcome.


Why would you need a crystal ball in order to manipulate the information in the marketplace and capitalise on fluctuations?

Surely, as long as you don't hold a position in the market when the results come out, the final results don't impact your profits?


The "crystal ball" was my attempt at making an analogy for a situation in which the outcome is held equal. Perhaps it was unnecessary or clumsy as analogies go.

Read my post and mentally strike out the crystal ball analogy, and to your point, a lot of what I was saying still holds true.


One added wrinkle is that some people may have a positive incentive to make inaccurate bets, if they have something riding on the perception of the outcome, that's sufficiently important to them to be worth spending the money pumping up the perception. Whether that's feasible depends on the size of the market, but if InTrade drives even some of the news cycle, and if $100k can move the InTrade needle on a relevant issue, then blowing $100k on it is essentially advertising spend, an attempt at image-boosting.


The issues do muddy the waters for using them as prediction markets. It is awesome, however for the savvy investor.

My experience has been they are far, far more accurate than the media. It is the nature of the accuracy that is interesting, however. They come to decisions well in advance of the media -- weeks or even months early. A good example would be this last national election cycle, the prediction markets had Rick Perry and Michelle Bachman virtually closed out while their media coverage was still treating them as viable candidates.

They aren't always right in the long run, but they converge on the right answers much sooner than anything else I've seen, Nate Silver's efforts included.

The biggest problem is that in the US they are either illegal (deemed to be gambling) or just too small (IEM).


> but if InTrade drives even some of the news cycle, and if $100k can move the InTrade needle on a relevant issue, then blowing $100k on it is essentially advertising spend, an attempt at image-boosting.

True. Little enough good it did the Romney whale on election day, though: he handed $4m as a gift to all the other Intrade users, and it didn't move the needle anywhere.


Your initial thesis is not supported by your observations, which anyway are problematic.

(1) This is not a "fundamental problem." Not every participant in the NYSE is a savvy investor, either.

(2) This was also true of the automobile market. It didn't stop Henry Ford. This is a serious incidental problem, but not a fundamental one.

(3) The best way to make money in a prediction market is to be able to predict the outcome of the predictions. You can also try to do what you're suggesting, and may have some success. Anyway, the evidence is that prediction markets work, both for hedging and for knowledge prediction.


The best way to make money in a prediction market is to be able to predict the outcome of the predictions.

I don't think this says quite what you meant. :-) As it stands, it can be read as saying that you can make money by predicting what other people believe, which is in agreement with the parent's #3. (And which is also true--as I noted just upthread, the author of the article in the OP did exactly that by buying and then selling McCain bets for the 2008 election.)


This is a pointless nit pick, but two can play at that game.

The outcome of the predictions is that all the correct predictions resolve to 1 (or 100% or what have you) and all the incorrect predictions resolve to 0.

Technically, I said what I wanted to say. Technical correctness is the best kind of correctness. ;)


All very good points. I had worked some years ago on a prediction market site which attempted to merge 3 mechanisms for gaining collective intelligence: Polling, paramutual betting, and full buy/sell market. It was motived by the fact that full blown market simulations are a steep learning curve for the non-investor, but that person has a valuable opinion nonetheless. Never did much with it.


Considering that I upvote pretty much every gwern.net article I see (the guy rarely disappoints) and that there's probably a fairly cohesive Overcoming Bias/Less Wrong demographic doing the same, how long will it take before we're banned as a voting ring?

(Anyone selling futures for that?)


If I'm right about the HN readership, gwern.net articles are going to receive upvotes from a much larger population than just the intersection of HN and LessWrong. Furthermore, if there is cohesion with respect to gwern's stuff, then that cohesion would either disappear when it comes to other submitters (if it's simply tribal allegiance) or we'd see it with other articles of interest (if it's based on shared interests).

If the cohesion disappears with other submitters, then any voting ring detection would have to be overly sensitive to pick up on your love of gwern. We'd hear about a lot of false positives.

If the cohesion is strong enough to warrant mention and it persists across other domains, then you'd probably see some trouble even without gwern.net submissions.


If daringfireball upvoters never got banned, I doubt you have anything to worry about.


Do you actually click on the link? Do you read some of the text, even if it's just a couple of paragraphs? Then I don't see a problem.

If you just upvote without bothering to learn what the article is about, then I think it beats the point of the voting mechanism.

Otherwise, there should be no problem, no?


There was a prediction markets company that YC funded in its second-ever batch: Inkling Markets. (http://inklingmarkets.com) It's still going, from what I understand through enterprise sales.

Also, for those of you that haven't heard Intrade is shut down and going through some complicated legal proceedings. Their former founder/CEO died climbing Mount Everest a couple of years ago, and I don't think the company ever fully recovered.

(I used to do a lot of work in prediction markets.)


Not just that, their financial situation suddenly became 'murky' and they shut up shop without letting customers withdraw their balances. As I understand, it is still unclear whether or not they have the cash to pay back everyone yet.


They don't, but judging from their messages on their homepage, they've gotten forbearance from their biggest creditors.


I'd never really heard of prediction markets before this post. Does anyone know the reason prediction markets are legal but other forms of online gambling such as poker are not?

Edit: Apparently they've just recently started using real money at some prediction markets: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Prediction_market#Legality


It's a big idea of Overcoming Bias'[1] Robin Hanson[2] along with a proposed governing method based on it called the futarchy[3].

[1] http://www.overcomingbias.com/tag/prediction-markets (easily one of top 5 blogs on the Internet)

[2] http://hanson.gmu.edu/ideafutures.html

[3] http://hanson.gmu.edu/futarchy.html


There's a big difference between a prediction market and a decision market, which is what futarchy is. Mencius Moldbug expounded on this quite a while back in this post:

http://unqualified-reservations.blogspot.com/2010/02/pipe-sh...

I won't go into much detail (the post is worth reading), but his basic point (which I agree with) is that the reason a prediction market works (when it works) is that the only incentive governing people's bets is their beliefs about the expected probabilities of outcomes. But this can only work if the bets people make are themselves statistically independent of the outcomes, and in a decision market they obviously can't be, since people's bets determine the outcome. (In the post Moldbug gives an actual real-world example of a market which gets manipulated in exactly this way.)


I worked for a company that tried to sell prediction markets (we worked on the Policy Analysis Market, if anyone remembers that debacle), and the legality is one of the biggest sticking points.

It was pretty easy to sell the idea, but invariably once the contract landed in the legal department they'd put the brakes on, and we'd have to do some contortions involving play money that gets converted to real money and so forth. Once you start taking the real money out of the equation the results are a bit more suspect.

Nevertheless we did manage to convince a major media company, a couple large pharma companies, and an advertising company to set up some small scale prediction markets.


"other forms of online gambling such as poker are not"

That, of course, depends where you are - in some countries online gambling is completely legal.


My impression was that they were sort of ignored because they had academic/research value as cover.

I believe the Fed's recent interest in them had something to do with Intrade closing down.

Here's a snippet from a forum thread that's relevant:

http://forums.randi.org/showthread.php?t=125104

From Wikipedia: Because online gambling is outlawed in the United States through federal laws and many state laws as well, most prediction markets that target U.S. users operate with "play money" rather than "real money": they are free to play (no purchase necessary) and usually offer prizes to the best traders as incentives to participate. Notable exceptions are Intrade/TradeSports, which escapes U.S. legal restrictions by operating from Dublin, Ireland, where gambling is legal and regulated, and the Iowa Electronic Markets, which operates from the University of Iowa under the cover of a no-action letter from the Commodity Futures Trading Commission and allows bets up to $500.


They aren't legal in the US generally. A few like the Iowa Electronic Market have a special exemption and very low upper limits on spending. Others like Betfair and Intrade when it existed are hosted in other countries, e.g. Ireland.


Yeah, DARPA got spanked for wanting to set one up[1] and Jim Bell got personally destroyed[2] for writing about them[3] from a radical political viewpoint.

[1]http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Policy_Analysis_Market

[2] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Jim_Bell

[3] http://www.outpost-of-freedom.com/jimbellap.htm


Right, and it had nothing to do with the fact it was proven he was using false identity documents to conceal money from the IRS. No sir. He was imprisoned just for writing an essay.


They were surveilling him were before the IRS charges. Not normal in a standard tax evasion matter.


Also, do people try to influence the outcome itself? For example, couldn't you ask: "When will X person die." And then someone could bet a huge amount of money on it, and then go kill that person?


You're thinking of Assassination markets [0]

[0] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Assassination_market


I find assassination markets a fascinating concept: I wrote a short story about them ( http://gwern.net/fiction/The%20Ones%20Who%20Walk%20Towar... ) and pondered whether they might be a successor to Silk Road (http://gwern.net/Silk%20Road#future-developments probably not).


I think you try to setup the market so that X dies of natural causes. So that at least it is more work than to rub someone out outright.


In some jurisdictions the determinant is "game of skill" versus "game of chance".


This is a good article. However if anyone is interested in following it, they should know that when there are multiple bets available, the simple Kelly criterion falls apart.

See http://www.elem.com/~btilly/kelly-criterion/ for a much fuller explanation of the result, and why it is true. (I keep meaning to automatically optimize the multiple bet version of it.)


Good link. I was writing a reply to make a couple of points but the page says it best:

"Many people will tell you to bet less than the Kelly formula says to bet. Two reasons are generally given for this. The first is that gamblers tend to overestimate their odds of winning and so will naturally overbet. Betting less than the Kelly amount corrects for this. The other is that the Kelly formula leads to extreme volatility, and you should underbet to limit the chance of being badly down for unacceptably long stretches."

The volatility is huge; you have a 50% chance of losing half your bank over time even if you bet correctly. Not many people can cope with those spikes in gains and losses!


That is why the JavaScript tools I wrote to go with the article can give you percentiles on where you would be after different numbers of trials. That's explicitly so that people can develop intuition about how much they need to underbet to stay within their comfort levels.


Now imagine prediction markets with the twist proposed by Jim Bell: everybody bets on a day a person will die. If that day passes or the person dies before, you lose the money to those who predicted the right day.

Now who can know for sure when somebody dies? Exactly.

Frankly I'm amazed something like this hasn't taken off on the deep web yet. Tor + Bitcoin should do it.

[1] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Assassination_market [2] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Jim_Bell


What's the status of Intrade? Will it be back? (http://www.intrade.com/v4/home/latest-news/)


Tangential, but I took a class with one of the professors in the linked paper (Sethi). It was a great class - many of the homeworks and exam questions were based around Intrade. (We didn't trade any actual money, but it really helped to illustrate the concepts of financial economics, which can get very abstract).


There were investigations of money laundering after the most recent presidential election. They ran into problems letting people from the USA make predictions. I think they are on their way out, they are basically gone already. Sad, since I loved going there!


Hey, I've created a site for making/tracking predictions called The Red Book (http://rdbk.net/). It's simple, just Will/Won't votes on predictions with a little gamification added to encourage community involvement. Just thought I'd plug it here if anyone is interested.


I'm still waiting for a good Bitcoin-based prediction market. I think that would be a nice application for the cryptocurrency.


Isn't this what http://betsofbitco.in does?


They do, but extremely poorly. I criticize them in the OP:

> One might wonder why I don't use the fairly active [Bets of Bitcoin](https://en.bitcoin.it/wiki/Bets_of_Bitcoin) prediction market; that is because the payout rules are [insane](http://betsofbitco.in/help) and I have no idea how to translate the "total weighted bets" into actual probabilities. Betting blind is never a good idea.


It's not a prediction market. It's just a badly-designed betting site.


A friend of mine is "working" on that. I can put you in touch if you want to encourage him.


I saw this mentioned the other day: https://www.predictious.com/


If you are interested in prediction market type betting and got friends who like the same, you might like http://www.bespokebets.com which lets you setup your own market easily and for free (play-money - and yes talking my book)


nice article, but I don't use the same strategy as you describe...

I was looking at prediction market recently, and tried a few free-to-play websites such as Inkling. I ended up on swissnoise (http://go.swissnoise.ch). They use virtual money for trade, but with real-money prizes which is very nice! Plus I have the feeling of helping research in this field (it's developed by some university).


Since your not really investing in anything, prediction markets are like gambling. You might as well bet on sports games.

As for their utility, the predictions are about as accurate as any other prediction, which is usually completely worthless. Might work ok for the boring stuff, but show me evidence that prediction markets can forecast the next 9/11, the next iPhone, or the next Arab Spring.


But you are investing with something, namely your own money, and it is this that gives the prediction markets value. Anyone can shout out their silly predictions, but if they have to back them up with cash, then the predictions tend to get better. The article has a quote that sums it up well:

"The usual touchstone of whether what someone asserts is mere persuasion or at least a subjective conviction, i.e., firm belief, is betting. Often someone pronounces his propositions with such confident and inflexible defiance that he seems to have entirely laid aside all concern for error. A bet disconcerts him. Sometimes he reveals that he is persuaded enough for one ducat but not for ten. For he would happily bet one, but at 10 he suddenly becomes aware of what he had not previously noticed, namely that it is quite possible that he has erred."


Thanks, but I don't need you to explain the theory behind prediction markets to me. I agree that by forcing people to put money behind their predictions, they will be less subject to bias. But even without those biases, we're really bad at predicting the future. I suppose prediction markets might make accurate short term predictions for events which we already know a lot about. But the events that make the most impact in business, politics, and technology are inherently unpredictable. So I can't see the benefit behind prediction markets.

Furthermore: Nothing changes the fact that it's still gambling. You aren't providing liquidity. You're not funding a business venture. You're just betting on the likelihood of something happening. It's still gambling, and you might as well bet on horses. A great choice if you've got money to lose, but don't care for horses much.


the predictions tend to get better

Only if there is some actual predictive skill out there to begin with. For example, the article gives the example of a prediction market on coin flips: the winning strategy is to take any bet for less than $1 (assuming that the payoff on a successful prediction is $2). But in short order, everyone who does not play that strategy will go bankrupt, and then there will be no more betting, because everyone remaining in the market will only take a bet at less than $1, but nobody will be willing to offer one. In other words, if there is an obvious limit to how well something can be predicted, the market will reach that point and then stop--no further betting will happen.


Not true at all! A golden example is Betfair's 'exchange games' markets, where they let players bet on fair, computer-managed card games. The markets are always exactly prcied-up. Some punters are playing, but even without the 'mugs' you can just look at the order book to see the predictions.

For the coin flip, you'd still have people asking for odds of 50.1% and others offering odds of 49.9% - you then can just look at the spread to discover the market prediction.


The markets are always exactly prcied-up.

Isn't this in agreement with what I said? I didn't say that the market prices would not reflect the expected predictions. I said that once that happens the market will stop moving, which appears to be exactly what you're saying:

you can just look at the order book to see the predictions.

In other words, there is a limit to how accurately people can predict the outcomes of these card games, and that limited predictive accuracy is what the market reflects. The real question is, how much betting volume is there for a given, fixed card game, once all the players in the market learn the odds? My expectation is that volume will decrease over time for a given, fixed card game, because if the game is fair, the betting is zero-sum, so players who know the optimal strategy will never bet among themselves (since you can't make money on average at zero-sum bets), and players who don't know the optimal strategy will go bankrupt.

Obviously if you introduce a new card game, the above doesn't apply; that would be the equivalent of adding, say, six-sided dice to the coin flip betting site: now there's a new set of odds to be learned, so there will be a new period of trading as market players learn the optimal strategy for this new game.

For the coin flip, you'd still have people asking for odds of 50.1% and others offering odds of 49.9%

Would any actual bets happen at these odds? What makes you think so? An occasional new player might try this, but he would end up losing money, and all the long-term players know that would happen, so they won't try it. Why would they?

Or do you just mean that people would be posting these asks/offers, but nobody would be accepting them? If so, then, once again, this is in agreement with what I was saying; no actual activity would be taking place in the market, but the asks/offers would accurately reflect the market's best available prediction--which is the best possible prediction, hence no money can be made in the market because trades are zero-sum.


I was writing to highlight your seeming disagreement with the text you quoted:

the predictions tend to get better

You seemed to be saying that this was not the case, citing a coin flip. My counter argument is that a real-world prediction market for (effectively) a coin flip tends towards a 'perfect' prediction. It can then stay in this steady-state regardless of whether or not any fool continues to bet; you just have to glance at the order book of unmatched bets to discern the prediction.

So, the predictions do tend to get better, even if you have unskilled participants. Or are you saying "predictions only get better if people are good at predicting", which would be stating the bleeding obvious, right?

(Disappointingly, Betfair's exchange games still seem to have money traded on them, and they run these games every minute of the day.)


I wasn't saying the predictions never change; I was saying that they will only change as long as there is knowledge about the outcome that has not yet been priced into the market. The market "not changing" does not mean it does not have a market price: it just means that the market price is constant (and that therefore there is no trading happening, except for the occasional new player entering and quickly losing money by playing a non-optimal strategy). You are saying the same thing, just in different words.

the predictions do tend to get better, even if you have unskilled participants

This statement as it stands is way too strong, which is why I originally objected. The correct statement is: "predictions will tend to get better as long as it is possible for the average skill level of the market participants to increase". You're right that participants don't have to start out being skilled; but the average skill level of the participants does have to be able to change for the market's predictions to change.

In the coin flip prediction market, that can't happen (or at least it can't happen for very long), because the optimal strategy for betting on coin flips is so obvious. In the Betfair card games, there is some scope for increasing participant skill, but there can't be very much if the games are fair; people will fairly quickly figure out the optimal strategy for any given game, and soon after that the market will stop trading if the players are rational. (You appear to agree with this, since you say it's "disappointing" that Betfair's games continue to have money traded on them.)

Of course these are simple examples; what about real-world prediction markets? What about, for example, betting on sports games? My sense is that a similar effect occurs there: the average skill level of the long-term market participants is relatively unchanged over time, and therefore the accuracy of the predictions that can be extracted from the order book is relatively constant over time. The reason money is still made in these markets is that there is a basically inexhaustible supply of new players who think they know more than they actually do, and who therefore quickly end up losing their money to the long-term players--much the same thing that happens in casinos.


If there is a better method for prediction, and a prediction market exists, you can arbitrage the difference to make money and bring accuracy to the market.


This is the essence of prediction markets.

Prediction markets pay for information to become public (if not the source).


> As for their utility, the predictions are about as accurate as any other prediction, which is usually completely worthless. Might work ok for the boring stuff, but show me evidence that prediction markets can forecast the next 9/11, the next iPhone, or the next Arab Spring.

See the IARPA geopolitical prediction contest, on exactly that sort of topic. I am an active participant in the GJP prediction market ( http://gwern.net/Prediction%20markets#iarpa-the-good-jud... ). The contest is not yet over, but there's already clear rankings of skill (contrary to what you say,most people cannot predict worth a damn) and IIRC, IARPA has said that the aggregate predictions from GJP & DAGGRE (more prediction markets) are better than its existing experts.


Well, part of the point is that by predicting, you get better at predicting! And the utility there is getting better at recognizing biases and being a more rational human being, which pays dividends in all sorts of aspects of life.



I realize there's not a perfect solution. But in this case, the imperfect solution isn't even helpful. The events they can predict reliably are things already obvious to most people. And the events they can't predict are usually the ones that carry the most impact. What's worse, they give us a false sense of security, letting our guard down because we think we have the answers.

There is a better solution: Accept that most people don't know anything, and reasonably prepare for any disaster looming in the future.


I predict that the sum of my cards will be closer to 21 without going over than the dealer's will.


Gambling.




Applications are open for YC Summer 2022

Guidelines | FAQ | Lists | API | Security | Legal | Apply to YC | Contact

Search: